Moral relativism is
the denial of moral universalism:
that there is only one true morality.[1] If a morality is a (formal
or informal) system of norms for judging choices and actions, policies and
character-dispositions, and the like, as morally good or bad, right or wrong,
virtuous or vicious—then moral relativism says two things: first, (1) more than one morality is correct, and second, (2) there are different, but
equally correct moralities which judge the same act, by the same agent, in the
same circumstances, as having opposite moral qualities.[2] That is: there are some
acts that are morally right according to one correct morality and morally wrong
according to another, equally correct morality.[3]
The proponent of moral
relativism need not say that every actual morality is equally correct. Some
moralities may be superior to others. This kind of relativism must deploy some
set of norms to judge moralities, and (presumably) these norms will not be
moral norms themselves. That is, the judgment that one morality is inferior
that that another morality is superior is (presumably) not itself a moral judgment.[4]
According to the
“pluralistic relativism” of David B. Wong, the truth conditions of a moral
judgment (e.g. “It is morally right that Sarah obey her mother in this case”)
vary from one morality to the next because the meanings of moral concepts (such
as moral rightness) are relative to a morality’s norms specifying, for example,
when the value of honoring parents is overridden by values of privacy and
autonomy, or vice versa. Since different moralities place more or less relative
importance on different values, what it means to have an overriding moral
reason for an action is not the same in every correct morality. The moral
judgments of parties representing different moralities may be in practical
conflict while both being true because each applies a different concept of
moral rightness. There are, however, universal constraints on moralities,
derived from human nature and from the functions of morality. A culture’s
concept of rightness could not be recognized as a proper moral concept if it did not meet these universal constraints.[5]
On Gilbert Harman’s version
of moral relativism, the meaning of the moral concepts employed in a moral
judgment is determined by an implicit agreement about moral norms between the
one issuing the judgment and the agent whose action is being judged. This “pure
version” of relativism does not allow moral judgments properly to be made about
the actions of an agent who is outside of the judge’s community. In Harman’s
view, only those who share the same implicit agreements about moral norms can
be in genuine moral disagreement.[6]
The following are some
objections that may be raised against moral relativism. (1) Moral relativism
makes nonsense of claims of moral improvement: for example, the claim that the
dominant American morality of today which recognizes the moral wrongness of
slavery is an improvement over the dominant American morality of the 18th
century which regarded slavery as morally permissible. (2) Moral relativism
cannot make sense of one’s making a moral judgment fallibilistically: that is,
sincerely judging something is morally right while acknowledging that one’s
judgment may be in error. (3) Moral relativism denies the phenomenon of genuine
moral disagreement by relativizing moral truth: when parties disagree, says
relativism, each one’s judgment is true relative to her own morality. Yet in
real cases of moral disagreement each party judges the other to be mistaken
categorically, and not just in error relative to one’s own moral standards. (4)
Moral relativism undermines the normative force of morality: why should someone
do what even her own community’s moral norms says she ought to do, if it is
just as good for her to do what some other morality says she ought to do
instead?
[1] David B. Wong, Natural Moralities, p. xii.
[2] A theory that
embraces the first claim but not the second would be a pluralistic but not a
relativistic theory of morality. Suppose one holds that there is a correct
deontological moral system and a correct consequentialist moral system, and
that there is no rational basis for judging one system to be superior or more
correct than the other. If it turns out, however, that there is no practical
difference between the two systems: if, that is, exactly the same set of
actions is morally right in each system, then this is pluralism without
relativism.
[3] Not every act must be judged to have
opposite moral qualities in different moralities. Moralities can be
significantly different without being opposed to one another in every moral
judgment.
[4] The cognitive expressivists
Simon Blackburn, Mark Timmons, and Terry Horgan, however, seem to say there is
no standard for judging another group’s morality that is not itself a moral standard. On this view, it seems
difficult to justify the moral standard one applies to the judgment of
another’s morality—or, indeed, to justify one’s positive judgment of one’s own
morality. But perhaps one’s endorsement or adoption of a morality is not the
kind of thing that admits of or requires justification?
[5] Wong, Natural Moralities, pp. 71-73.
[6] Wong, Natural Moralities, p. 74, interpreting
Gilbert Harman, “Moral Relativism Defended,” Philosophical Review 84 (1975):3-22, and Harman’s contribution to
Gilbert Harman and Judith Jarvis Thomson, Moral
Relativism and Moral Objectivity (Blackwell, 1996), pp. 32-46.
No comments:
Post a Comment